Its City Council has served notice
that the issue will be considered sometime soon, with the initial
contemplated legislation covering not just inside almost every place of
public commerce or within 25 feet of the entrance of such a place or in the
case of schools 200 feet, but also includes any publicly-owned property indoor
or outdoor. The only exceptions would be some lodging rooms, some assisted
living quarters, and places where large quantities of tobacco are sold or
manufactured. State law sets down minimum standards where smoking may be banned
but allows local governments to go further.
This argument occurs over three
dimensions. The economic component looks to see whether far-reaching bans would
impact negatively economic activity, which implies a loss of government
revenues as well. Opponents to bans historically in many different locations
trot out alleged evidence that bans would create such a negative impact.
However, in reality studies
from many different jurisdictions present a mixed picture. Some show that
negative impact, yet others show no significant impact and still others actual
improvement. Regardless, this argument if understood properly really should have
no bearing on the issue. After all, even advocates of smoking concede that the
activity at the very least harms those who engage in it, for there long has
been established strong association between the activity and disease and death,
most often from various forms of cancer, even without finding the causal
mechanism.
This means, contrary to the perception
of many, that government
expenditures related to smoking actually are lower as a result of its wider availability;
simply, Medicaid, Medicare, and Veterans Affairs expenditures would be higher
the less of it occurs because people would live longer and thereby have more opportunities
to have more health care needs. While the impact to private sector activity may
end up a wash, in the near term there would be a definitely negative impact to
government finances, both because of increased expenditures and because of
decreased revenues from tobacco taxes as use would decline. Yet the long term
may end up quite differently, as increased productivity through fewer illnesses
in a working lifespan and substitution away from tobacco-related activities
towards more productive pursuits may increase overall economic growth and
thereby tax take.
Still, if as all concerned
recognize a harmful impact from smoking to the user, saving lives should take
precedence over monetary considerations, mooting the economic argument. It’s
the extent to which lives can get saved, however, that affects the other two
arguments.
Without identification of the
precise causal mechanism, proponents of wide smoking opportunity argue that “secondhand
smoke,” or the direct exposure to nonsmokers of the by-product of smokers, and “thirdhand
smoke,” or residue left from smoking that can impact nonsmokers, do not pose a
health hazard. If accepting this, then they can wrap themselves in a civil libertarian
argument by saying, as they allege no deleterious effects exist for nonusers,
then it should not be banned as people are choosing to take the risk without
impact to others.
But conveniently ignored in the
assertion that one should have a right to smoke as an expression of personal liberty
is the competing liberty of having the right not to experience that smoke,
presenting a conflict where someone in order to exercise a liberty must deny
liberty to others. On numerical grounds, nonsmokers appear to win, as less
than a fifth of the American public smokes.
However, when speaking about
fundamental liberties, majorities don’t matter. Marxism may appeal only to the
logic- and fact-impaired, but free speech is considered so vital to the operation
of the republic that the few actually arguing for a Marxist state and society
are protected in their ability to do. Yet is smoking such an exercise of a
fundamental right so important to human freedom and functioning of the republic
that it must get privileged treatment?
Making this implication even less
tenable is that fact that certain people do suffer immediate harm casually
attached to smoking even by a faint whiff of smoke. Asthmatics, sufferers of
chronic obstructive pulmonary disease (ironically, often caused by smoking),
and those with other maladies that have as a side effect reduced pulmonary function,
such as muscular dystrophy, can go into immediate distress with even the most
casual amount of smoke particles entering their bodies. For them, smelling
somebody else’s smoke is not an annoyance and expression of rude and boorish
behavior, but potentially life-threatening, and their numbers continue to grow
as a proportion of the population as medical science increases amelioration
options that allow these people to live longer and with a higher quality of
life.
If there is a civil liberties case,
then, preference should be shown not to those who engage in a voluntary
activity to satisfy a craving, but to those who face involuntary threat to
their health. Upon acknowledging this, smoking advocates alter the argument to
say that those affected can remove themselves from the situation by patronizing
only establishments without smoking, where the business in question can choose
whether to permit it on premises. Naturally, this represents a sizable
concession in that it admits smoking may be banned on all public property in
order to allow all members of society access to these facilities, but does throw
up a bulwark in Louisiana around such places of commerce as bars and casinos.
Yet even this argument suffers
defeat on the basis of civil rights. As a minor concern, if few or no
establishments voluntarily disallow smoking in a given area, it means those
wishing to be employed in the hospitality or entertainment area that are
anywhere annoyed to compromised by smoke are moderately to severely restricted
in their employment options, impeding their abilities to pursue work in these
fields, even as a number of career options still would be open for them.
But as a major concern, this
environment would restrict the ability of those compromised easily by smoke or
its residue to participate in commerce. While just a small portion of the
public is mobility impaired to the extent that they needs ramps, wider doors, sufficient
aisle space, etc. to engage in commerce, it is not unconstitutional to require
that entities in commerce provide these even as they could cost the business
money. The same should apply to smoking, where, in essence, businesses of any
kind must supply clean air to aid the breathing-impaired public, even if its
numbers are small, in its ability to engage in the commerce.
Therefore, no compelling case
exists to not ban smoking on any of economic, civil liberties, or civil rights
grounds. And by New Orleans doing so, this could serve as a tipping point to
enact such measures in other Louisiana municipalities or, as some states have
done, statewide. Currently, the largest cities with measures close to these in
place are Alexandria and Monroe, but to have the state’s most significant city
follow can create momentum that accelerates the trend. Undoubtedly when the
measure comes up a pitched battle will ensue, but a ban as end product would
constitute clearly correct policy.
No comments:
Post a Comment